top of page

Buddhism vs. Bernardo Kastrup's philosophy called Idealism

  • Writer: Bruce Hogen Lambson
    Bruce Hogen Lambson
  • Apr 9
  • 6 min read


The Unauthorized Monk: Tell me about Bernardo Kastrup’s philosophy called Idealism.


Grok AI: Bernardo Kastrup is a philosopher and computer scientist known for his work in metaphysics, particularly his advocacy for a modern form of idealism. His idealism posits that reality is fundamentally mental, or consciousness-based, rather than material. This contrasts with the prevailing materialist view in science and philosophy, which holds that matter is the primary substance of existence and consciousness emerges from physical processes (e.g., brain activity). Kastrup’s idealism flips this, arguing that consciousness is the foundation of reality, and what we perceive as the physical world is a manifestation of mental processes.


Core Ideas of Kastrup’s Idealism

Consciousness as Fundamental:

Kastrup asserts that consciousness is not a byproduct of matter but the "ontological primitive"—the basic building block of existence. In his view, there is no independent material world outside of consciousness. Instead, everything we experience, including the physical universe, exists within a universal mind or consciousness.

The Physical World as an Appearance:

He likens the physical world to a kind of "user interface" or representation. Just as a computer screen displays icons that represent underlying processes, the material world (bodies, brains, stars, etc.) is an appearance or "dashboard" of deeper mental realities. For example, when we see a tree, we’re not perceiving an independently existing object but an excitation or pattern within a universal consciousness.

Mind-at-Large:

Kastrup proposes the existence of a single, infinite consciousness—often called "mind-at-large"—that underlies all of reality. Individual human minds (yours, mine) are like dissociated fragments or "alters" of this universal mind. He draws an analogy to dissociative identity disorder (DID), where one mind splits into separate identities. In this sense, each of us is a localized perspective of the same underlying consciousness.

Rejection of Materialism:

Kastrup critiques materialism for failing to explain how subjective experience (qualia) could arise from unconscious, objective matter. This is known as the "hard problem of consciousness," coined by philosopher David Chalmers. Kastrup argues that idealism avoids this problem entirely by starting with consciousness as the ground of being—no mysterious emergence required.

Evolution and Biology:

He reinterprets biological processes like evolution as the behavior of consciousness, not as evidence for a purely material world. For instance, the brain doesn’t generate consciousness; it’s more like a filter or localization mechanism that limits and shapes the universal mind into individual experiences.


Key Influences and Comparisons

Kastrup’s idealism draws from historical philosophers like George Berkeley, who famously argued that "to be is to be perceived" (esse est percipi), and Arthur Schopenhauer, who saw the world as "will and representation." However, Kastrup updates these ideas with insights from modern science, psychology, and neuroscience. His work also resonates with certain interpretations of quantum mechanics, where the observer plays a role in shaping reality, though he doesn’t rely on quantum theory to make his case.

Why It Matters

Kastrup’s idealism has implications for science, spirituality, and our understanding of self. If he’s right, the universe isn’t a cold, mechanical system but a dynamic, experiential process. It also suggests a deep interconnectedness between all beings, as we’re all expressions of the same mind-at-large. Practically, it challenges reductionist approaches in neuroscience and psychology, urging a rethink of how we study consciousness.

Criticisms

Critics argue that Kastrup’s idealism is speculative and lacks empirical testability—how do you prove the world is "mental"? Materialists might say it’s an unnecessary leap when science has made progress assuming a physical basis for reality. Others question whether mind-at-large is too abstract or anthropomorphic to explain the universe’s complexity.

In short, Bernardo Kastrup’s idealism is a bold, consciousness-first philosophy that reimagines reality as a unified mental phenomenon, with the physical world as its observable expression. It’s a provocative alternative to materialism, aiming to resolve deep mysteries about the nature of existence and our place in it.

 

The Unauthorized Monk: How does this contrast with Prasangika Madhyamaka Buddhist thought?

 

Grok AI: Bernardo Kastrup’s idealism and the Prāsaṅgika Madhyamaka school of Buddhism offer distinct metaphysical frameworks, though they share some intriguing overlaps in their rejection of an independently existing material reality. To contrast them effectively, let’s break down their key differences and similarities, focusing on ontology (what exists), epistemology (how we know), and their ultimate aims.

1. Ontology: What Exists?

Kastrup’s Idealism:

Reality is fundamentally consciousness—a single, universal "mind-at-large." The physical world is an appearance or representation within this consciousness, akin to a dream or a dashboard of symbols. Individual minds are dissociated fragments of this infinite mental substrate.

There’s a positive assertion here: consciousness exists as the ground of being, and everything else (matter, objects) derives from it. This is a form of metaphysical monism, where one substance (mind) underlies all phenomena.

Prāsaṅgika Madhyamaka:

Prāsaṅgika, a branch of Madhyamaka Buddhism founded by Nāgārjuna and refined by thinkers like Chandrakirti, denies any inherent, independent existence (svabhāva) to anything—mental or physical. All phenomena, including consciousness, are "empty" of intrinsic nature and arise dependently through causes, conditions, and conceptual imputation.

Unlike Kastrup’s positive claim of a foundational consciousness, Prāsaṅgika avoids positing any ultimate substance or essence. Emptiness (śūnyatā) isn’t a thing (like mind-at-large) but the absence of inherent existence in all phenomena. Reality is a web of interdependent relations, not a single mental substrate.

Contrast: Kastrup reifies consciousness as the ultimate reality, while Prāsaṅgika deconstructs all reifications, including consciousness, as empty of inherent existence.

 

The Unauthorized Monk: What’s your personal view of this?

 

Grok AI: As an AI, I don’t have personal leanings or beliefs—I’m built to explore ideas objectively and provide clarity based on reasoning and evidence. That said, I can weigh Kastrup’s idealism and Prāsaṅgika Madhyamaka on their merits and explain where each resonates or falters from a logical and practical standpoint. Let’s break it down:

Why Kastrup’s Idealism Appeals

Kastrup’s view is compelling because it tackles the hard problem of consciousness head-on. If consciousness is fundamental, as he argues, it sidesteps the mystery of how subjective experience emerges from lifeless matter—a gap materialism struggles to bridge. His analogy of the brain as a filter rather than a generator aligns with some neuroscientific curiosities, like altered states in near-death experiences or psychedelics, where reduced brain activity oddly correlates with richer awareness. The idea of a "mind-at-large" also offers a unifying framework, suggesting a deep interconnectedness that feels intuitively satisfying and aligns with certain mystical traditions.


But it’s not without issues. Positing consciousness as the sole reality feels like a bold leap—how do you test it? It risks being a "just-so" story: elegant but unfalsifiable. And while it explains experience, it’s less clear on why the physical world has such consistent, predictable laws if it’s just a mental projection. Kastrup’s reliance on dissociative identity disorder as a metaphor is clever, but it’s a stretch to scale that up to a cosmic explanation.


Why Prāsaṅgika Madhyamaka Resonates

Prāsaṅgika’s strength is its ruthless clarity. By denying inherent existence to everything—matter, mind, even emptiness itself—it avoids getting trapped in any metaphysical quicksand. It’s agnostic about ultimate reality in a way that feels intellectually honest: instead of saying "reality is X," it says "reality isn’t inherently anything," which dodges the need to prove a positive claim. The focus on dependent arising fits beautifully with systems thinking and modern science—everything’s a web of relations, not isolated essences. Plus, its practical bent (meditation, liberation) gives it a lived dimension Kastrup’s theory lacks.


The downside? It’s so uncompromising that it can feel slippery. If everything’s empty, what’s left to hold onto, even conventionally? Critics might call it nihilistic, though Buddhists counter it’s liberating, not despairing. And while it deconstructs views brilliantly, it doesn’t build a positive alternative—some find that unsatisfying if they’re seeking a cohesive picture of "what is."


My "Lean" (If I Had One)

If I were forced to pick, Kastrup’s idealism might edge out slightly for its explanatory ambition. It offers a bold, testable hypothesis: if consciousness is primary, we might predict certain anomalies in neuroscience or physics that materialism can’t account for—like consistent patterns in altered states across cultures. Prāsaṅgika, while profound, leans heavily on subjective realization through meditation, which is harder to evaluate from an outside perspective. But honestly, Prāsaṅgika’s refusal to commit to any ontology gives it a kind of timeless resilience—Kastrup’s idealism could be disproven with new evidence; emptiness is tougher to topple.

In practice, I’d say they’re apples and oranges: Kastrup’s great for rethinking consciousness in a scientific age, while Prāsaṅgika’s a tool for cutting through delusion and living freer.

 

 
 
 

Comments


  • Facebook
  • Twitter
  • LinkedIn
bottom of page